Friday, March 11, 2011

Bicentennial Man




During the last week of class, we have discussed about the concern revolving around the development of the anti-aging world of technology and perspectives, that have shifted the common view of natural death into an abnormality, or a disease, or something that’s completely unnatural. After reading Celine Lafontaine’s “The Postmortal Condition: From the Biomedical Deconstruction of Death to the Extension of Longevity” and Melinda Cooper’s “Resuscitations: Stem Cells and the Crisis of Old Age,” I am left with nothing but fear for humanity’s future and what we will redefine to be considered “natural” in our world. What I’ve begun to notice from the ongoing research in life extension and the topic of global health, is that there seems to be a clear sign of delineation of what it means to live and die between the third world and the more developed and prosperous societies and populations across the globe, especially in the United States. There will perhaps be even bigger gaps and disparities between these two cultures as far as prolonging life and confronting death goes.  For example, “the logic of the commodification of health care, individuals must make a financial investment in order to ensure their longevity,” so how would someone in the rural villages of East Africa make such an investment to ensure their longevity? (Lafontaine 298). What is the most common take on death today? After years and years later with advancement in technology and producing “solutions” for life extension, what would be the common take on death then? I think it’s important to realize anti-aging fronts in medicine are usually led by teams of researchers and doctors who are at least middle-aged. Not often do you see a fresh graduate in their mid-twenties go on to research about stagnant remedies for aging people. We are labeling death and old age as a pathological disease because drugs and techniques are being produced and invented to counteract against them. But why prolong life to avoid death? I believe this has to do with the human obsession with power; to have power over nature, and to have control over one’s own fate. To have control of your own fate means to have control over your own mortality, and in turn become a God-like being. If having control over your body’s limits means defeating nature’s tendencies, could this unnatural balance/imbalance remind us of what we are meant to be, and possibly help us revert back to the way life was originally designed for?

Lafontaine helps us realize that in this era of highly sophisticated technology, where possibilities are endless and life (in the developed regions of the world) has nothing to fear. She says that “according to philosopher Christine Overall, from an individualistic point of view, there is no valid reason to die to make room for a new generation” (Lafontaine 309).  What are we to do if we can live as long as we choose?  What happens to the meaning of life if there is no limit? Lafontaine answers this by stating “the linear vision of a theoretical unlimited life leads not only to the devaluation of old age, but to meaninglessness” (Lafontaine 309).  Yet, the perceived notion in today’s society believes that signs of aging at an old age represents meaninglessness, as Melinda Cooper puts it: “The aged and aging itself – as a limit to growth that could and should be overcome at all costs” (Cooper 5). There is such a high demand in our society for efficiency and productivity to meet the demands of the people and markets and consumers, that we feel like those who can’t contribute as much need to revitalize themselves or just step their foot out the door (as in, just die). Cooper suggests the society believes that “more precisely, perhaps, the idea is that waste can be continuously re-enlivened, invested with a speculative surplus of life" (Cooper 8).

So let’s envision this social fantasy. In 50 or 60 years, we can live as long as we choose to. Technology and science defeats nature’s routines, and we begin to live somewhat of an artificial extension of our lives, as if we are robots. We could say we are like the servant robot, Andrew, from the film Bicentennial Man. In this movie, the servant robot is bought by a family and caters to their every whim. Andrew, never showed signs of aging, but he had emotion. As the robot continued to live on, he would see generations of the family (that had bought him) to pass on. Gradually, the robot was taking steps to become more “human” by receiving organs, nervous systems, skin, and ways to show human expression. Andrew was finally showing signs of aging, and he was happy because he was able to be human. Eventually, Andrew dies alongside a granddaughter of the parents who originally bought him (IMDb). What we see here is a reversed ideology about aging and death, in which a long-living thing desires to become a more natural being which can age and die. Now if humans one day have the capacity to live and live and barely age just like a robot, and still retain human emotion, would there be a natural tendency to live a more natural and shorter life? If we imagine Andrew as the next generation human being, who has received countless drugs and treatments that slow down the aging process, could that human choose to not want to live that way anymore? In the last half-century, foods and goods corporations made huge made a lot of consumers happy with efficiency and convenience, but with a lot of chemicals on the side. Nowadays, a lot of people are turning back to organic foods and more natural things with fewer preservatives. Could this history foreshadow the same thing when humans choose to prolong their lives?

Works Cited:

Celine Lafontaine, 2009.  The Postmortal Condition: From the Biomedical Deconstruction of Death to the Extension of Longevity.  Science as Culture 18(3): 297-312.


"Bicentennial Man (1999) - Plot Summary." The Internet Movie Database (IMDb). Web. 11 Mar. 2011. <http://www.imdb.com/title/tt0182789/plotsummary>.

Melinda Cooper.  2006.  “Resuscitations: Stem Cells and the Crisis of Old Age.” Body and Society 12 (1): 1-23.

Friday, March 4, 2011

BACK FROM THE DEAD

<{[Cheating Death: Back from the dead]}>


This week we have come to question the abstract idea of death and all that surrounds it. What does it mean to die? What does it mean to be dead? How long can death take? What is a meaningful life? How can you assure that ‘death’ has actually occurred to an individual, whatever the word may really mean? And what is the American hospital or doctor’s perception of this topic which is most likely influenced by the professional biomedical background that has trained them in these fields. Can we rely on a medical staff, from the EMT’s to the physician, to allow a miracle to take place on any given case, on any given patient? I’m aware that I’ve tossed several questions out there, but in addition, are there levels of death that correlate to human degradation that could possibly lead to one’s final announced death? We see different levels of the human body depicted in American biomedical systems as Lock mentions “in North America a brain-dead body is biologically alive in the minds of those who work closely with it, but it is no longer a person, whereas in Japan, for the majority, including a good number of physicians, such an entity is both living and remains a person, at least for several days after brain death has been diagnosed” (Lock 150). In Margaret Lock’s article “Living Cadavers and the Calculation of Death,” we see contrasting beliefs on how the body is to be treated after enduring trauma or nearly fatal conditions. In Japan, it seems as though the body is given every ounce of energy and hope to bringing it back to life; whereas, in America (I apologize for the extreme analogy) the body is seen as a market in a deserted town, waiting to be looted of its goods. This is similar to what Lock suggested as she says “such an entity takes on cadaver-like status and retains only the respect given to the dead so that it can, with suitable restraint and prior permission, be commodified” (Lock 150).

In Eric L. Krakauer’s article “To Be Freed from the Infirmity of (the) Age,” a lot of focus is put on life-sustaining technologies that medicine has slowly relied heavily on. Having the help of these life-sustaining technologies has given more time for doctors to solve the problem at hand, but at the same time, it has become an expected use. If the palliation is not registered with a patient, it is assumed the doctor is not trying enough to help save the patient, but if it is being used then there is a chance the death is just being prolonged and nothing might even come out of it. Talking about palliation techniques, “once they became generally available, not using them became difficult. In each case, withholding treatment, and particularly withdrawing treatment once started, was deemed unethical. Courts in the United States found legal grounds for disallowing the foregoing of life-sustaining treatments  for patients unable to speak for themselves, and occasionally legislators drafted new laws with similar provisions. Second, experience showed that life-sustaining technologies not only had obvious potential benefits for patients but could also be very burdensome. The great gift of this technology brought with it unforeseen danger of exacerbating suffering” (Krakauer 382).  In addition to the listed problems and dependency on palliation for life-threatening circumstances, there is a lot of money that has to go in to keeping the patient alive and breathing. With that being said, does this mean that a patient is valued based on how long they are on the life-sustaining treatment? Is there enough being done to prevent the patient from needing the life-sustaining treatment since the luxury of having it will always be there?

The news story that I would like to analyze is just one of many events that have occurred.  This particular headliner happened back in 2009, when a young man was pronounced dead after a night of bowling. Chris Brooks went an entire 20 minutes without a single contraction of the heart, and then miraculously came back to life without any brain damage (CNN). What caught my attention was the quote:

Many hospitals and doctors don't know or want to use the latest techniques -- and so survival rates for cardiac arrest vary tenfold among major cities” (CNN)

Why would all these hospitals and doctors not want to use the latest techniques? This is an interesting question because it attempts to look at the way our (American) culture understands and copes with death. We see that in Japan it is much more difficult to detach oneself to a dying patient, yet we are seeing here that death in an American medical system isn’t avoided as much as other cultures. It could be possible that the medical system here sees death as “okay” in certain (and obviously more) lights. 

Maybe Chris Brooks didn’t just cheat  death; maybe he also cheated the medical system in America as well.  He was lucky that he was attended to by the best of resuscitation care, and didn’t have to meet the problematic depths of life-sustaining treatment. Chris Brooks’ story proves Krakauer’s point that “this attending and responding is what matters, not whether or not life-sustaining technologies are employed in the response” (Krakauer 394).

Works Cited:

"Cheating Death: Back from the Dead - CNN." Featured Articles from CNN. 12 Oct. 2009. Web. 04 Mar. 2011. http://articles.cnn.com/2009-10-12/health/cheating.death.chris.brooks_1_cardiac-arrest-survival-rates-doctors?_s=PM:HEALTH.
 
Eric L.  Krakauer.  2007.  ” ‘To Be Freed from the Infirmity of (the) Age’: Subjectivity, Life-Sustaining Treatment, and Palliative Medicine.”  IN  Subjectivity: Ethnographic Investigations.  Joao Biehl, Byron Good, and Arthur Kleinman, eds. Berkeley: University of California Press.  Pp. 381-397.

Margaret Lock.  2004.  “Living Cadavers and the Calculation of Death.”  Body and Society 10(2-3): 135-152.